1134
you are viewing a single comment's thread
view the rest of the comments
[-] lmfamao@lemm.ee 1 points 4 days ago

:::thinking Okay, let's break down John's latest response. He's doubling down on the idea that systemic analysis and individual accountability are separate, and that focusing on institutions is more practical than critiquing individuals. He's using historical examples like the Nuremberg trials and the civil rights movement to argue that we should focus blame on the top and not on lower-level participants.

First, I need to address his claim that proportional accountability exempts lower-tier individuals. The Nuremberg example is key here. John says they focused on leaders, but in reality, they did prosecute lower-level enablers, not just architects. That's an important point. He's trying to create a binary between leaders and followers, but in reality, systems require collaboration at all levels.

Then there's the resistance argument. John frames resistance as something only heroes do, which dismisses the moral agency of ordinary people. I need to point out that while resistance is costly, it's not about heroism but about recognizing moral imperatives. Historical examples like the Underground Railroad show that even in dire circumstances, people made choices, and those choices mattered even if not everyone could make them.

Whistleblowers like Manning and Snowden—John dismisses them as exceptions with unique access, but their roles were actually not that high up. Their actions demonstrate that even those in lower positions can make impactful choices. Highlighting Hugh Thompson stopping the My Lai massacre is another good example of someone lower in hierarchy taking a stand.

The civil rights movement is another area. John claims they targeted specific businesses, which they did, but they also shamed individuals who upheld segregation. Rosa Parks wasn't just a victim; she was a trained activist making a deliberate choice. This shows that individual actions and systemic change are interconnected.

John also creates a false binary between systemic reform and individual accountability. The anti-war movement's success wasn't just due to policy changes but also cultural shifts that made military service less appealing. This ties into the idea that stigma and cultural change are part of systemic reform, not separate from it.

His argument about the working class needing "realistic expectations" ignores the fact that moral agency still exists even under constraints. While systemic change is crucial, recognizing individual complicity doesn't negate the need for that change—it complements it. Solidarity means fighting for better options while acknowledging the moral dimensions of current choices.

Finally, John's pragmatism is actually resignation. Real change requires challenging both systems and individuals. Cultural shifts are part of systemic change, and dismissing individual accountability undermines the potential for broader transformation. It's not about blaming the exploited but recognizing their role in perpetuating systems, even under duress.

Need to make sure the response is clear, removes any numbered lists or markdown, and maintains a slightly less inflammatory tone while still addressing each point logically. Avoid strawmanning John's arguments, instead accurately reflecting his points and countering them with historical examples and logical consistency. Emphasize that systemic and individual accountability are intertwined and necessary for meaningful change. :::

Your rebuttal rests on a series of selective interpretations that obscure the interdependence of systemic and individual accountability. Let’s clarify:

You argue for “proportional accountability” but define it so narrowly that it functionally absolves anyone outside leadership roles. Nuremberg, however, explicitly rejected this hierarchy of guilt. While prioritizing architects, the trials also prosecuted industrialists, bureaucrats, and doctors—not because they held equal power, but because systems of oppression require collaboration at multiple levels. Proportionality isn’t about exempting participants—it’s about calibrating scrutiny to their role. Your framework risks reducing accountability to a binary: architects bear guilt, while participants bear circumstance. This isn’t nuance—it’s evasion.

Resistance is costly, yes—but so is complacency. The Underground Railroad conductor risked death, but we don’t retroactively excuse those who didn’t resist; we honor those who did. Their courage doesn’t demand heroism from everyone—it exposes the moral stakes of participation. To say “most couldn’t” doesn’t negate the imperative to act; it indicts the system that made resistance lethal. Dismissing dissent as “exceptional” rationalizes passivity.

Your claim that whistleblowers like Manning and Snowden had “extraordinary access” distorts reality. Manning was a low-ranking analyst; Snowden, a contractor. Their roles weren’t unique—their choices were. The My Lai massacre was halted not by a general but by Hugh Thompson, a helicopter pilot who intervened. Moral courage isn’t about hierarchy—it’s about recognizing ethical breaches and acting, however imperfectly. To frame their actions as outliers is to ignore that systems crumble when enough cogs refuse to turn.

The civil rights movement did target institutions, but it also stigmatized individuals—Bull Connor, George Wallace, and the white citizens who upheld segregation. Rosa Parks wasn’t a passive victim of buses; she was a trained activist making deliberate choices. The movement understood that systemic change requires both policy shifts and cultural condemnation of those who enforce oppression. Boycotts didn’t just bankrupt businesses—they made racism socially untenable.

You frame systemic reform and cultural critique as opposing strategies, but they’re symbiotic. The draft wasn’t abolished through congressional debate alone—it collapsed under the weight of draft-card burnings, desertions, and a generation rejecting militarism. Stigma isn’t a substitute for policy—it’s the cultural groundwork that makes policy possible.

Your “realistic expectations” argument conflates constraints with absolution. The teenager enlisting to escape poverty still chooses to join an institution they know causes harm. To say they have “no choice” denies their moral agency. Solidarity isn’t excusing participation—it’s fighting for a world where survival doesn’t require complicity in empire.

Finally, your “pragmatism” mistakes resignation for strategy. True change requires uncomfortable truths: systems and individuals must both be challenged, complicity persists even under constraint, and moral clarity isn’t about purity—it’s about refusing to normalize oppression.

this post was submitted on 29 Mar 2025
1134 points (88.4% liked)

Memes

49459 readers
1178 users here now

Rules:

  1. Be civil and nice.
  2. Try not to excessively repost, as a rule of thumb, wait at least 2 months to do it if you have to.

founded 6 years ago
MODERATORS